European Journal of the History of Economic Thought

Taylor & Francis
Taylor & Francis
ISSN: 09672567, 14695936

Are you a researcher?

Create a profile to get free access to personal recommendations for colleagues and new articles.
SCImago
Q2
WOS
Q3
Impact factor
0.6
SJR
0.342
CiteScore
1.5
Categories
Arts and Humanities (miscellaneous)
Economics, Econometrics and Finance (miscellaneous)
History and Philosophy of Science
Areas
Arts and Humanities
Economics, Econometrics and Finance
Years of issue
1993-2025
journal names
European Journal of the History of Economic Thought
EUR J HIST ECON THOU
Publications
1 718
Citations
6 484
h-index
27
Top-3 organizations
University of Graz
University of Graz (55 publications)
University of Pisa
University of Pisa (20 publications)
University of Lausanne
University of Lausanne (18 publications)
Top-3 countries
Italy (139 publications)
France (121 publications)
United Kingdom (86 publications)

Most cited in 5 years

Found 
from chars
Publications found: 741
Aquinas on the Enumeration of the Virtues
Stöpfgeshoff A.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2025 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
Abstract Daniel Russell has argued that virtue ethics requires a criterion for enumerating the virtues and suggests that reasons for action distinguish them (2009). This paper explores and defends Thomas Aquinas’s (ca. 1225–1274) view that virtues are distinguished by what makes us good in overcoming the difficulties we face. Aquinas’s account explains why agents can seemingly perform different virtuous actions for the same reasons while still satisfying the demands set by Russell for a theory of enumeration.
The Moral Worth of Mixed Actions
Chan B.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2025 citations by CoLab: 0
Referees for 2024
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2025 citations by CoLab: 0
Is Self-Discrimination Disrespectful?
Bengtson A., Pedersen V.M.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2025 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
Abstract Victims of oppressive (e.g., sexist, racist or ableist) structures sometimes internalize the unjust norms that prevail in society. This can cause these victims to develop preferences or make decisions that seem bad for them. Focusing on such cases, we ask: is self-discrimination disrespectful? We show that some of the most sophisticated respect theories fail to provide any clear guidance. Specifically, we show that the widely recognized view that respect has two dimensions—an interest dimension and an autonomy dimension—delivers completely opposite verdicts depending on how these two dimensions (and the relation between them) are specified. A main takeaway point is that we need to distinguish between at least four different respect-based views. Whether self-discrimination caused by internalized oppression is disrespectful depends on which view one supports.
The Eudaimonist Ethics of al-Farabi and Avicenna by Janne Mattila, Leiden, Brill, 2022, p. 247, €99.00 (hb), ISBN: 978-90-04-50647-3
Muhammad A.N., Ulviana, Anggraini R.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2025 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
Janne Mattila’s The Eudaimonist Ethics of al-Farabi and Avicenna offers a systematic exploration of how al-Farabi and Avicenna, two prominent figures in classical Islamic philosophy, developed distinct ethical frameworks grounded in the concept of eudaimonia. This book examines how both thinkers navigated classical Greek influences, especially those of Aristotle and Plato, while integrating Islamic philosophical principles to develop unique ethical systems. The work addresses the relative lack of focused scholarship on these philosophers’ ethical thought, emphasizing that their ethics extend beyond a mere synthesis of Greek philosophy into original contributions grounded in psychology, cosmology, and metaphysics. This book is divided into two major sections: happiness and virtue. It first delves into happiness as the final end for human existence, presenting how al-Farabi and Avicenna interpreted Aristotle’s function argument and contemplative pleasure. Mattila argues that for both thinkers, human flourishing lies in intellectual activity, particularly theoretical contemplation, a stance rooted in their metaphysical, cosmological, and psychological views. The second section investigates virtue, focusing on how both philosophers define virtues not just as traits of moderation but as pathways toward intellectual and spiritual perfection. These ethical ideals are explored through a variety of primary sources, many of which also engage with political philosophy, further demonstrating the interdisciplinary nature of their thought. One of the book’s strengths is its reconstruction of ethical theories from fragmented texts, offering new perspectives on al-Farabi and Avicenna’s moral philosophy. The book reveals an interesting tension in their works between the Aristotelian concept of virtue as moderation of bodily passions (metriopatheia)—which can also be found in Plato's Republic—and the ideal of liberation from bodily passions (apatheia), as exemplified in the Stoa and Neoplatonism and prefigured in Plato's Phaedo. Mattila convincingly argues that both al-Farabi and Avicenna resolved this tension by positioning intellectual and moral virtues within a framework of philosophical progression. Despite the depth of analysis, the book raises questions about the accessibility and application of such ethical ideals in modern contexts. Some sections might benefit from further elaboration, particularly regarding potential inconsistencies in these thinkers’ views on virtue. However, Mattila succeeds in demonstrating the relevance of the ethical thought of al-Farabi and Avicenna for contemporary discussions on human flourishing, virtue ethics, and the philosophy of happiness. This work is a valuable contribution to the field of Islamic ethics and philosophy, appealing to scholars interested in the intersection of classical Greek philosophy and Islamic thought, as well as those exploring the metaphysical foundations of ethics. By shedding light on lesser-studied dimensions of the intellectual legacies of these two philosophers, the book invites readers to consider the richness and originality of medieval Islamic philosophy.
Harm, Insignificant Effects, and the Morality of Procreation
Pinkert F.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2025 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
Abstract Several authors have argued that we ought to have fewer children in order to reduce our contribution to climate change. Proponents of this view generally hold a moderate version of the view, according to which it is still permissible to have one or two children per couple. One recent exception is Chad Vance’s paper “Procreation is Immoral on Environmental Grounds” in this journal, in which he argues that procreation is always, or almost always, morally impermissible. I argue, first, that Vance is mistaken in conceding that his radical position holds only if individual acts of procreation can make a difference, rather than being only a causally insignificantly contribution to collective harm. Instead, given his assumptions, he should hold on to the radical view that we ought to have no children at all. Second, I argue against Vance’s strongest argument for his radical view. Vance argues that procreation harms others, and that obligations to avoid harming rule out the demandingness considerations that are used to support a permission to have one or two children. However, contrary to paradigmatic cases of harming, any procreation-related harms result not only from procreators’ actions, but also from our collective failures to rapidly reduce emissions. This complex causal structure undermines Vance’s rejection of demandingness considerations. I conclude that the moderate view that we may have one or two children per couple survives Vance’s criticism.
Tusian Perfectionism
Hadisi R.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2025 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
I offer a reconstructive reading of Ṭūsī’s (1201–1274) account of natural goodness in the Naserian Ethics. I show that Ṭūsī’s version of Aristotelian ethics is especially well-suited to accommodate an intuition that is hard to integrate into a theory of natural goodness: Human good is nobler or more elevated than animal and vegetative goods. To do this, I analyze Ṭūsī’s discussion of the relationship between different kinds of perfection from non-living material compounds to vegetative, animal, human, and divine beings. I close by noting that, depending on our reading of Ṭūsī’s conception of divine beings and their perfection, his proposal might come at a cost to his Aristotelian naturalist ambitions for ethics.
Breaking Up Rationally
Villiger D., de Vries B.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2025 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
Abstract The end of a long-term romantic relationship ranks among the most stressful and momentous events in life. Thus, the decision of whether to break up with someone whom one has been with for many years should generally be made very carefully. Unfortunately, decision theory is often thought to be unable to provide rational guidance in such high-stake life choices due to the outcomes’ presumed transformative character. The present paper shows how agents can rationally decide whether to leave their romantic partner even if the decision is transformative. It does so by using a novel five-level account of transformative decision-making, which can also be used for other key life choices, and which is the first to integrate in a systematic way several approaches for making (certain types of) transformative decisions that have been proposed in recent years.
The Better Choice? The Status Quo versus Radical Human Enhancement
Hayenhjelm M.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2024 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
AbstractCan it be rational to favour the status quo when the alternatives to the status quo promise considerable increases in overall value? For instance, can it be rational to favour the status quo over radical human enhancement? A reasonable response to these questions would be to say that it can only be rational if the status quo is indeed the better choice on some measure. In this paper, I argue that it can be rational to favour the status quo over a radical improvement such as human germline genetic enhancement. First, I distinguish between three different meanings of the “status quo.” Then, I argue that the status quo enjoys modal and epistemic advantages that sometimes translate into other advantages. I propose eight parameters for comparison between the status quo and radical options. These parameters weigh in favour of the status quo but can be outweighed by the benefits of change. Each of these parameters needs to be assessed from case to case. I defend what I refer to as an Open Status Quo position over a Fixed Status Quo position. The former is decision-specific and does not entail a commitment to remaining with the status quo in later decisions. Lastly, I address the objection that an Open Status Quo position risk slipping into a Fixed Status Quo position that would, in turn, block radical progress, change, and discovery.
Moral Attention and Bad Sentimentality
Jamieson L.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2024 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
AbstractIn this paper, I challenge standard views of the moral badness of sentimentality defended by art critics and philosophers. Accounts based on untruthfulness and self-indulgence lack the resources to both explain the badness of bad sentimentality and to allow that there are benign instances. We are sometimes permitted to be sentimental even though it is self-serving. A non-moralistic account should allow for this. To provide such an account, I first outline a substantive view of the ideal of unsentimentality by turning to Rainer Maria Rilke’s Letters on Cézanne. Rilke celebrates the artist for his unsentimental love of his subjects and “untiring objective wakefulness” to them. I then turn to Iris Murdoch’s ethics of attention (itself influenced by Rilke) to explain why this ideal is so difficult to live up to in practice, the various ways that we fall short, and what our failures mean. What Murdoch contributes is both a sense that the lovingly attentive attitude that Rilke describes is morally—and not just artistically—important and a compassionate account of the human egocentrism that inhibits it. By thinking of sentimentality as a failure of moral attention, we can appreciate how particular instances differ from one another. Sentimentality can console us in difficult times or can gratify our egos; it can be a form of escapism or can rigidly enclose reality; and it can be harmlessly self-serving or a selfish failure to morally attend to the other when it counts. I conclude by outlining some ways that being seen with Cézanne-like moral attention can matter to us.
Commemoration and Constriction
Lim C.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2024 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
In analysing the problems with commemorative artefacts, philosophers have tended to focus on objectionable monuments that honour inappropriate subjects. The problems with such monuments, however, do not exhaust problems with a society’s public commemorative landscape – the totality of public commemorative artefacts in general, and the institutions involved in their creation and maintenance. I argue that a public commemorative landscape can implicate authoritative ideas, including stereotypes about people in virtue of their group membership. This contributes to what I term hermeneutical constriction – a situation in which people are given reason to rely on an authoritative subset of the totality of hermeneutical resources that they actually have access to. Critiquing and resisting these problems with a public commemorative landscape that contributes to hermeneutical constriction is fraught with difficulties. Attempts to do so render activists vulnerable to a range of serious criticisms.
Fittingness and Well-Being
Hooker B.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2024 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
Abstract Mental states (beliefs, emotions, moods, desires, etc.) towards things can fit or fail to fit those things. Perhaps actions can fit or fail to fit the situations in which they are done. This paper explores whether having fitting mental states and doing fitting actions can constitute additions to a person’s well-being. The paper first discusses the desire-fulfilment theory of well-being. Then the paper considers hedonistic theories of well-being and criticises the recent proposal from Rossi and Tappolet that well-being consists only in fitting happiness. Then the paper turns to the objective list theory of well-being and Badhwar’s Aristotelian theory. In this context, the paper considers Bruno-Niño’s recent argument for fitting attitudes as a part of well-being. Finally, the paper explores whether, on the objective list theory and Badhwar’s theory, doing fitting actions constitutes an element of well-being. The upshots are that fittingness is not an element of well-being according to some theories of well-being and that it is an element of well-being either contingently or necessarily according to other theories of well-being.
Racist Monuments: The Beauty is the Beast
Lai T.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2024 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
AbstractWhile much has been said about what ought to be done about the statues and monuments of racist, colonial, and oppressive figures, a significantly undertheorised aspect of the debate is the aesthetics of commemorations. I believe that this philosophical oversight is rather unfortunate. I contend that taking the aesthetic value of commemorations seriously can help us (a) better understand how and the extent to which objectionable commemorations are objectionable, (b) properly formulate responses to aesthetic defences of objectionable commemorations, and c) help us explore aesthetic solutions—for example, artistic interventions as counterspeech—to objectionable commemorations. Here, I propose that the aesthetic value of objectionable commemorations can amplify the force of the objectionable messages conveyed, and the moral disvalue of objectionable commemorations can hinder our appreciation of their aesthetic value. These two considerations shall help us answer the practical question of what to do about objectionable commemorations of apparently good aesthetic value. Both, I shall argue, give us further reason to remove, replace, recontextualise, or even vandalise objectionable commemorations. Sometimes we need to save the art from its own immorality to best respect its aesthetic value.
Self-Defense Against Conditional Threats
Venezia L., Rivera-López E.
Q1
Springer Nature
Journal of Ethics 2024 citations by CoLab: 0  |  Abstract
The aim of this paper is twofold. First, we argue that killing a Conditional Threat usually involves an unnecessary act of self-defense, so killing this aggressor is usually morally impermissible. We defend this thesis by showing that this case is fundamentally similar to a case involving an Unconditional Threat in which the victim can flee to safety although this involves incurring a minor cost. Second, we analyze the thresholds of maximal harm that victims are required to bear before they are permitted to defend themselves by harming their aggressors related to the conditions of necessity and of proportionality. We argue that the maximal harm a victim is required to bear sanctioned by the condition of necessity is, all else being equal, lower than the maximal harm that a victim must bear sanctioned by the condition of proportionality. This result is relevant for determining in which cases victims may use lethal force against Conditional Threats, both in the individual case and also in the case of war.

Top-100

Citing journals

100
200
300
400
500
600
700
800
900
1000
Show all (70 more)
100
200
300
400
500
600
700
800
900
1000

Citing publishers

200
400
600
800
1000
1200
1400
1600
Show all (70 more)
200
400
600
800
1000
1200
1400
1600

Publishing organizations

10
20
30
40
50
60
Show all (70 more)
10
20
30
40
50
60

Publishing organizations in 5 years

1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
Show all (70 more)
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8

Publishing countries

20
40
60
80
100
120
140
Italy, 139, 8.09%
France, 121, 7.04%
United Kingdom, 86, 5.01%
Austria, 71, 4.13%
Germany, 69, 4.02%
USA, 65, 3.78%
Switzerland, 32, 1.86%
Australia, 31, 1.8%
Netherlands, 29, 1.69%
Canada, 20, 1.16%
Brazil, 19, 1.11%
Portugal, 17, 0.99%
Japan, 14, 0.81%
Belgium, 13, 0.76%
Spain, 11, 0.64%
Greece, 10, 0.58%
Estonia, 8, 0.47%
Ireland, 8, 0.47%
Finland, 6, 0.35%
Sweden, 6, 0.35%
Argentina, 5, 0.29%
Russia, 4, 0.23%
China, 4, 0.23%
Turkey, 4, 0.23%
Denmark, 3, 0.17%
Israel, 3, 0.17%
Bulgaria, 2, 0.12%
Hungary, 2, 0.12%
India, 1, 0.06%
Luxembourg, 1, 0.06%
New Zealand, 1, 0.06%
Reunion, 1, 0.06%
Slovenia, 1, 0.06%
Montenegro, 1, 0.06%
Show all (4 more)
20
40
60
80
100
120
140

Publishing countries in 5 years

10
20
30
40
50
60
France, 57, 14.47%
Italy, 26, 6.6%
United Kingdom, 25, 6.35%
USA, 24, 6.09%
Germany, 16, 4.06%
Switzerland, 13, 3.3%
Canada, 11, 2.79%
Austria, 6, 1.52%
Brazil, 6, 1.52%
Japan, 6, 1.52%
Estonia, 5, 1.27%
Belgium, 5, 1.27%
Netherlands, 4, 1.02%
Russia, 3, 0.76%
Portugal, 3, 0.76%
Argentina, 3, 0.76%
Greece, 3, 0.76%
China, 2, 0.51%
Australia, 2, 0.51%
Ireland, 2, 0.51%
Finland, 2, 0.51%
Sweden, 2, 0.51%
Bulgaria, 1, 0.25%
Hungary, 1, 0.25%
Denmark, 1, 0.25%
India, 1, 0.25%
Spain, 1, 0.25%
Slovenia, 1, 0.25%
10
20
30
40
50
60